大桥未久AV手机在线观看

    1. <form id=sFmQbIMHg><nobr id=sFmQbIMHg></nobr></form>
      <address id=sFmQbIMHg><nobr id=sFmQbIMHg><nobr id=sFmQbIMHg></nobr></nobr></address>

      Talk delivered at the Touch Me Festival, Zagreb, December 2008
      The Reproductive Revolution: selection pressure in a Post-Darwinian World

      The Reproductive Revolution
      Selection Pressure in a Post-Darwinian World

      Here are three predictions about life one thousand years from now:

      1) Suffering of any kind will be biologically impossible. Our descendants will lead lives of genetically pre-programmed bliss whose worst lows surpass today's peak experiences. A thousand years hence, the heritable hedonic set-point of ordinary waking life will have been ratcheted upwards so that everyday existence feels sublime.

      2) Our genetically enhanced successors won't grow old and die, but will be effectively immortal, barring accidents which mean certain brains have to be restored from digital backup.

      3) Posthumans will be innately smarter than us, not just in the narrow autistic sense of intelligence measured by contemporary IQ tests, but also a more empathetic intelligence. To use a non-scientific term, our descendants will be "wiser" than contemporary humans.

      These are bold claims. They could of course be completely mistaken: futurology doesn't have a brilliant track-record. However, I'm going to argue why these three seemingly unrelated developments - superhappiness, superlongevity and superintelligence - are intimately linked. We are on the brink of a revolution in reproductive medicine - the coming era of designer babies, a fundamental transition in the evolution of life in the universe. Evolution will shortly cease to be "blind" and "random", as it has been for the past four billion years. Instead, intelligent agents are going to choose and design genotypes in anticipation of their likely behavioural and psychological effects. Specifically, prospective parents will increasingly choose the genetic makeup of their future children rather than playing genetic roulette. Natural selection is going to be replaced by "unnatural" selection.

      But first, let us outline a very different, bioconservative vision, perhaps best represented today by the distinguished geneticist at University College London, Professor Steve Jones.

      Two Contrasting Views of Future Human Evolution

      1) BIOCONSERVATIVISM: ["The End of Evolution"?] "If you want to know what Utopia is like, just look around - this is it", says Professor Jones in a Royal Society debate in Edinburgh. In a talk1 entitled "Is Evolution Over?" Prof. Jones says: "Things have simply stopped getting better, or worse, for our species." Professor Jones explains how there were three components to human evolution – natural selection, mutation and random change. “Quite unexpectedly, we have dropped the human mutation rate because of a change in reproductive patterns.”

      “In ancient times half our children would have died by the age of 20. Now, in the Western world, 98 per cent of them are surviving to 21”, says Professor Jones in a recent interview2 with The Times. The mutation rate is also slowing down. Although chemicals and radioactive pollution could cause genetic changes, one of the most important mutation triggers was advanced age in men. "Perhaps surprisingly, the age of reproduction has gone down - the mean age of male reproduction means that most conceive no children after the age of 35. Fewer older fathers means that if anything, mutation is going down."

      It's worth adding that some scientists and right-wing commentators go further than Steve Jones. They argue that because nominally more intelligent people have fewer children than nominally less intelligent people, then the intelligence of the human species as a whole is actually going to decline. This prediction isn't borne out by the long-term increase in IQ scores over the last century, the "Flynn Effect". However, believers in the so-called dysgenic fertility hypothesis counter that it is possible for genotypic IQ to decline even while phenotypic IQ rises throughout the population, at least in the short run. They explain this paradox by environmental effects such as better schooling, improved nutrition, and even television viewing.

      By contrast to the bioconservative perspective:

      2) BIOREVOLUTION: Human evolution is about to accelerate. Selection pressure isn't going to slacken. On the contrary, we're on the eve an era of unnatural or artificial selection - a different kind of selection pressure, but a selection pressure that will be extraordinarily intense, favouring a very different set of adaptations than traits that were genetically adaptive in the ancestral environment on the African savannah.

      Let's quickly review some background. The Human Genome Project (HGP) was the international scientific research project that aimed to determine the sequence of chemical base pairs of our DNA: the genetic make-up of our species. Researchers identified, physically and functionally, the 25,000 or so genes of the human genome. The project was formally declared complete to a 99.99% accuracy in 2003, though in reality there are a lot of loose ends to be tied up. The full implications of our deciphered code have scarcely been glimpsed. They may take centuries to unravel.

      Currently [2009], if you want your whole genome of three billion odd base pairs sequenced, the price is several thousand dollars. This figure is prohibitively expensive for most people. [In 2015, the price had fallen to around one thousand dollars.] But in a decade or so, the cost on some estimates could be as little as ten dollars. Whatever the exact price or timing, the cost of access to one's own source code is poised to collapse. Routine access to one's personal genome will usher in an era of personalised medicine - individual drugs, dosages and gene therapies targeted at the individual rather than the scatter-gun approach we see in clinical pharmacology (and recreational drug use) today.

      Yet we're not just heading for an era of personalized medicine - we're on the eve of an era of personalized reproductive medicine: "designer babies", to use the popular term. The phrase suggests something frivolous, akin to designer clothes. But choosing the genetic make-up of your child may soon become the badge of responsible parenthood - as distinct from throwing the genetic dice and hoping they roll the right way, as now. A reluctance to pass on harmful code to our children won't just apply to obvious autosomal dominant conditions like the neurological disorder Huntington's disease. What prospective parent, if offered the choice, is deliberately going to pass on genes for haemophilia, sickle-cell anaemia or muscular dystrophy? It has been estimated that on average we each carry four lethal recessive genes. In a future of post-genomic reproductive medicine, the selection pressure against, say, the cystic fibrosis allele, the cause of the most common life-limiting autosomal recessive disease among people of European heritage, is going to become intense, as indeed is selection pressure against a whole range of genes that cause or contribute to physical disease. Currently, we're used to Googling prospective partners on the Net to find out more about them. Looking ahead, what responsible prospective parent will neglect to check their partner's DNA - and their own - before having children? This doesn't mean that anyone who wants a child will reject an asymptomatic partner who carries a recessive copy of a "nasty" gene. Instead, responsible parents can use preimplantation genetic diagnosis and germline gene therapy to ensure that potentially harmful genes like the recessive cystic fibrosis allele aren't passed on to their children.

      Genetic Roulette versus Designer Babies

      Yet how about heritable psychological traits, "personality genes", that contribute to psychological pain? Not merely is there no consensus on whether some of their less pleasant variants should be classed as pathological, here too things are much more complex technically than for monogenic disorders like cystic fibrosis. This is because there is no such thing as a single gene "for" depression or anxiety disorders or jealousy or obsessive compulsive disorder (OCD) and so forth. But there are alleles and genotypes that predispose to depression or anxiety disorders or jealousy or obsessive compulsive disorder - and other polygenic, multifactorial psychological conditions. So if there is a particular allele - a variant gene - that makes it, say, 5% more likely that a particular trait such as low mood or chronic anxiety will be expressed, or an allele that makes its bearer 5% more or less anxious or more or less depressive, then what percentage of prospective parents will purposely choose the less pleasant variant for their children? Yes, there are numerous complications, for instance pleiotropy, where a single gene influences multiple phenotypic traits; alternative splicing, whereby a single gene may produce different proteins in different settings; genomic imprinting, a parent-dependent form of gene expression; non-Mendelian inheritance in the form of transgenerational epigenetic effects; and so forth. More generally, critics of the new genetic medicine worry about creating "designer personalities". Other things being equal, however, most informed parents will presumably choose the more compassionate option for their child. Indeed one Oxford Professor of Ethics goes further. Julian Savulescu argues that we are are morally obligated to select genetic blueprints for children with the greatest chance of leading the best life: what Prof. Savulescu dubs the Principle of Procreative Beneficence.

      This conjecture isn't premature. For example, people who inherit two copies of a "short" version of the chromosome 17 serotonin transporter gene, 5-HTTLPR, have an 80 per cent chance of becoming clinically depressed if they experience three or more negative life-events in five years. By contrast, genetically resilient people who inherit the long version have only a 30 per cent chance of developing mental illness in similar circumstances. If offered the choice via preimplantation diagnosis (PGD), would you opt for the short or the long serotonin transporter gene variant for your future child? Or would you decline to choose, putting your faith in God or Mother Nature?

      Right now, of course, this kind of scenario still sounds far-fetched. Later this century and beyond, are prospective parents really going to enroll for courses in behavioural genetics and molecular biopsychiatry before having kids? For sure, certain genetic decisions are in principle straightforward, for example gender selection, or whether to pass on a cystic fibrosis allele. Such decisions are taken by some prospective parents in a few countries already. But other genetic decisions will be much more complicated, not least for "mood genes" that help determine a person's average level of well-being or ill-being over a lifetime.

      For what it's worth, I personally think that taking advanced courses in behavioural genetics, or at least seeking genetic counselling, will be morally incumbent on anyone before s/he assumes the immense responsibility of having a child. Yet this kind of education is unlikely to be widespread for the foreseeable future. The argument presented here doesn't depend on it. Instead, in an era of mature reproductive medicine, we may forecast an abundance of user-friendly software tools to enable prospective parents to take responsible genetic decisions - as distinct from blindly taking their chances in the genetic lottery of Darwinian life. For the exponential growth in computing power can be harnessed to a new growth industry of sophisticated baby-authoring software. So the average parent will no more be required to understand molecular genetics than the average contemporary Windows PC user is required to understand machine code. And the parallel goes further. If it's ethically acceptable to spend hours redesigning your Windows PC desktop the way you like it, then why not at least take a few hours to make sure that your future child is psychologically and physically healthy too?

      Of course, such authoring tools open up an ethical and regulatory minefield of gargantuan proportions. Yet so does sexual reproduction: playing the genetic equivalent of Russian roulette with a child's life.

      Recalibrating the Hedonic Treadmill.
      OK, maybe prospective parents will choose to avoid alleles and allelic combinations associated with depression or anxiety disorders or schizophrenia when they prepare to have children. But what grounds are there for thinking that the average hedonic set-point of humankind as a whole will be ratcheted ever upwards? Recall that we all have a kind of inbuilt hedonic treadmill that prevents most of us from remaining extremely happy or extremely miserable for very long - though of course extreme misery can seem like an eternity while it lasts. Our hedonic treadmill tends to have an approximate hedonic set-point around which we fluctuate over time. This hedonic set-point crudely determines the average level of subjective well-being or ill-being that most people experience throughout a lifetime. Of course we're all buffeted by external events, both pleasant and unpleasant, that affect us acutely for good or ill; but over time, we mostly revert to a [partly] heritable individual mean. In some people, the hedonic set-point tends to be fixed below the Darwinian average: such people have a gloomy temperament - what the ancients would have called an excess of black bile. In other people, the hedonic set-point is fixed above average: they are temperamentally optimistic. Some people's mood oscillates sharply, other people are more equable. But the current range of hedonic diversity aside, why may we predict that the typical default state of well-being of the human population is going to increase indefinitely - even after genes predisposing to anxiety disorders and clinical depression have been weeded out of the gene-pool?

      The plain answer is that we can't know for sure. So this is speculation. Yet here is a thought-experiment. Imagine that you have the option of choosing the genetic dial-settings of the hedonic set-point of your future child: the degree to which he or she is temperamentally depressive or happy - or superhappy. To keep things simple, I won't yet consider the richer forms of emotional well-being, just normal hedonic tone, which we know is partly heritable. What average level of hedonic tone would you choose for your future child on a 10-point scale? [Here again I am being deliberately simplistic.] On the unscientific basis of a few straw polls conducted over the years, I'd estimate that most people if pressed would opt for a hedonic 8 or 9. Yet a surprising number of respondents say "10": they would like their children to be as temperamentally happy as possible.

      Realistically, perhaps only a minority of prospective parents will initially want to have children disposed to be naturally superhappy by contemporary norms. But most parents will want happy children, as distinct from depressive, moody, anxiety-ridden children. Not least, happy children are more fun to raise. Happy, resilient, self-confident children are also more likely to be "successful" over-achievers in the traditional Darwinian sense: we needn't suppose that prospective parents care only about the happiness of their future kids: many parents-to-be are of course highly ambitious for their offspring. Anyhow, on this argument, the average, genetically constrained set-point of emotional well-being of our species is destined to rise over time as a reflection of these individual parental choices, as tomorrow's enhancement technologies shift social norms of well-being and become the next generation's remedial therapies. The depressive realism of one century may become the affective psychosis of the next. Over time, an analogous selection pressure may be exerted in favour of alleles and allelic combinations predisposing to high intelligence - and perhaps even genius and supergenius - although here any contribution to enhanced quality of life will be indirect. In any event, over a whole spectrum of physical and psychological traits, we may predict that germline enhancement will become germline remediation as the average level of biological well-being improves across human society. As biophysicist Gregory Stock notes in Redesigning Humans (2002), "The arrival of safe, reliable germline technology will [...] transform the evolutionary process by drawing reproduction into a highly selective social process that is far more rapid and effective at spreading successful genes than traditional sexual competition and mate selection." Thus the tempo of world-wide mood-enrichment may accelerate.

      Critically, the genetic mood-enrichment conjecture doesn't hypothesise the future existence of any mega-project to make a happier world. The possibility of such a pan-global project can't be excluded - grandiose and fanciful as the idea of some kind of Hedonistic Imperative (1995) now sounds. Currently only the tiny Himalayan kingdom of Bhutan officially exalts Gross National Happiness (GNH) over Gross National Product (GNP). If hedonic enrichment were internationalized and pursued with scientific rigour, then the selection pressure against nastier Darwinian genotypes would be even more severe than anticipated here. Now personally, I advocate a world-wide Abolitionist Project laid down as official United Nations policy. Not least, only a global mega-project can ever extend the abolition of suffering to the rest of the living world. Ecosystem redesign, cross-species depot-contraception, and eventually rewriting the whole vertebrate genome can't be achieved via private initiative. However, such a mega-project isn't imminent. Less extravagantly, global mood-enrichment may be the collective outcome of billions of personal reproductive decisions made by individual parents-to-be during the next century and beyond.

      Phrased in the language of designer babies, the prospect of species-wide hedonic enrichment evokes sinister images - even though it promises to make the world a much happier place. Do we really want parents controlling the destiny of their future children? But we have to be careful about how we frame the issue here. Just as physical good health is empowering, and doesn't determine what you do with your life, likewise being temperamentally happy and psychologically robust doesn't determine what you actually do with your life either. Like physical health, mental health tends to empower rather than constrain. Genetically hardwired mental superhealth is potentially even more empowering. It makes you psychologically indestructible. It stops you ever becoming depressed or anxiety-ridden - and suffering the crippling loss of life-opportunities that such conditions entail. Moreover, in the future anybody who isn't satisfied with aspects of their core personality, and who doesn't want to use consciousness-altering drugs to change it, can practise somatic gene therapy. We won't always be at the mercy of a scrambled mix of our parent's genes as now, whether those genes have been passed on by accident or design.

      Future Nociception: The End of Physical Pain?

      So far I've talked about the abolition of suffering, and how psychological pain can be genetically eliminated over time. But what about the terrible scourge of raw physical pain? Surely, the sceptic might wonder, genes that promote pain-sensitivity in response to tissue damage will be as adaptive one thousand years from now as they are today - and as they were in the ancestral environment. So the prediction that one thousand years hence, the worst experiences that anyone undergoes will be richer than today's peak experiences sounds like a pipe-dream. How is this even technically possible, let alone sociologically realistic?

      Well, there is a short-to-medium term answer and a longer-term answer. Let's consider the short-to-medium term options first.

      The Cyborg Solution versus Radical Recalibration.
      At present there are different "natural" genetic variants that promote varying degrees of pain-sensitivity e.g. variant alleles of the gene SCN9A coding for the a-subunit of the voltage-gated sodium channel Nav1.7 in nociceptive neurons; the mu opioid receptor gene; and the gene encoding catecholamine-O-methyltransferase (COMT). Few prospective parents in the future are going to want kids who are hypersensitive to physical pain. Most parents, if given the choice, will presumably seek no more than mild-to-modest pain-sensitivity for their offspring. Thus if genetically planned parenthood ever becomes the norm, then our pain thermostats (or "algostats", as one might call them) are likely to be genetically re-set over time too.

      But this recalibration doesn't actually abolish suffering, it just diminishes its prevalence and intensity when physical pain occurs. Moreover, as attested by rare cases of congenital anaesthesia, children born without any capacity to suffer pain are currently liable to undergo all manner of life-threatening medical complications. So does this mean we are stuck with pain in some guise or other for ever?

      No, though there are formidable technical challenges to overcome. If we are to abolish physical pain altogether, I think there are two long-term options. These two options are not mutually exclusive, but I will consider them separately. Recall how silicon (etc.) robots with the right functional architecture can get by fine without the nasty "raw feels" of phenomenal pain; they can be programmed to avoid and respond flexibly and adaptively to noxious stimuli. Clearly, there is a distinction between the physiological function of nociception and the subjective experience of phenomenal pain; they are dissociable even in organic robots like us, not just our inorganic counterparts. So likewise, in theory future humans could computationally offload everything nasty or routine onto prosthetic devices, nanobots and the like, preserving only the life-enriching forms of sentience and discarding the ugly Darwinian junk. This is what we may call the Cyborg Solution. The main advantage of the Cyborg Solution in the long run is that it permits maximum lifelong bliss for all sentient life. Thus its ultimate adoption would seem mandatory on a classical utilitarian ethic. But assuming that we don't go down the cyborg route, there is another option. In principle, we can radically reset the scale of the pleasure-pain axis in the mind/brain. All that is needed for an organism to respond adaptively to a changing and potentially hostile environment is informational-sensitivity to fitness-relevant changes - including the binary opposition "wonderful" versus "not-quite-as-wonderful" - regardless of the tidal range of our emotions on an absolute hedonic scale; a narrow compass of pleasure gradients can in theory play a role analogous to pain gradients in some victims of chronic pain syndrome today.

      This hypothesis is counterintuitive. One might imagine that if people always feel more-or-less superwell - both physically and psychologically - then they won't be motivated to act circumspectly; and therefore they will tend to hurt themselves, whether physically or emotionally or both. Who could respond adaptively to the world if consumed by a perpetual whole-body orgasm? Yet this doesn't follow. As we know today, the happiest people, the keenest life-lovers, tend to be the most motivated people. It's depressives who tend to be unmotivated. Yes, there are forms of happiness associated with indolence, for example opiated bliss. But there are also forms of happiness associated with intense motivation, forward planning and goal-directed behaviour, so called hyperdopaminergic states. Either way, our descendants, and possibly our elderly selves, will have a choice of what kinds of physical and emotional well-being they want to enjoy, and a choice of what kinds of genetic predisposition to pass on to the next generation. If you don't want to bring any more suffering into the world, then your only option right now is not to have children. In the future, however, we'll be able to have cruelty-free children with a clear conscience - on that score at least.

      Gradients of Bliss?
      What's true of physical pain and depression is true of other negative states of mind. Thus the prediction that life a thousand years hence will feel orders of magnitude better than now isn't a claim that posthumans will all be uniformly happy, or that future life will be perfect, whatever that might mean. Indeed one can argue that discontent is the motor of progress, and that the functional analogues of discontent are likely to endure one thousand years from now, just as the raw feels of discontent exist at present. Admittedly, it's hard to know whether fourth millennium (post)humans will be endowed with anything even functionally resembling the same core emotions that define our lives today. The molecular signature of some kinds of emotion, for example disgust, panic or jealousy, might be abolished altogether, both phenomenally and functionally, whereas genes and regulatory code for novel life-enriching emotions may be customised and spliced into the genome. Our perceptual and cognitive architecture is likely to be genetically reshaped too - probably in ways beyond the contemporary human imagination. But such innovation isn't essential for an improved quality of life. The functional analogues of anxiety and depression could still persist and yet life could always be subjectively wonderful - since it's technically possible to decouple functional role from the subjective texture of unpleasant experience as we feel it now.

      Critically, I'm not arguing that our descendants will enjoy uniform bliss, and certainly not that they will be manic or "blissed out", simply that their genetically constrained floor of comparative ill-being will be higher than our absolute ceiling of well-being. Continual germline-enhancement across the generations will create a novel motivational system. Its mechanisms of emotional homeostasis will transcend the Darwinian pleasure-pain axis. Thanks to the unfolding Reproductive Revolution, there will be continual selection pressure in favour of the biology of a subjectively improved quality of life. Equating net value and net happiness in the manner of classical utilitarian ethics may or may not be simplistic; but acknowledgement of the connection between enhanced value and enhanced emotional well-being is common to a whole range of ethical systems, both religious and secular. Few ethical systems give no weight to emotional well-being. Thus if a piece of music sounds a thousand times more enchanting than its predecessor, or if a work of art looks a thousand times more beautiful to behold than anything physiologically possible at present, then I think the default assumption must be that such overpowering beauty is indeed a good thing - in the absence of cogent arguments to the contrary. The new germinal choice technologies allow the creation of subjectively valuable experience on a truly prodigious scale. So other things being equal, we should embrace their use.

      Spiritual well-being?
      The approach I've sketched so far probably sounds crudely reductionist. But one needn't interpret superhappiness in just a narrow one-dimensional sense. Take, for example, spirituality and spiritual well-being. ? In future, if you are very spiritual and want to have hyperspiritual children, then you can opt to over- or under-express the relevant genes or allelic combinations promoting a spiritual temperament; and perhaps ultimately design angelic "spiritual" genomes for your children. Indeed if you want to be naturally superspiritual yourself and don't want to take entheogenic drugs, then you could use autosomal gene enhancement and add extra copies or over-express variants of alleles and allelic combinations associated with spirituality. Secular rationalists, on the other hand, may prefer to lay the genetic foundations of a more worldly well-being.

      To take another example of multi-dimensional well-being, prospective parents may be able to choose genes and genotypes associated, not just with intelligence in the simple-minded conventional sense, but with an increased capacity for empathy, involving functionally amplified mirror neurons and enhanced social cognition. Prospective parents will have the opportunity to endow their kids with an enriched oxytocin system, leading to greater trust, generosity of spirit, and pro-social behaviour, potentially with immense benefits for society as a whole. Such scenarios are of course speculative.

      A Reproductive Elite?

      An obvious question arises. Won't these new reproductive technologies be solely for the rich, or at least mainly for members of the prosperous developed nations who can buy the best genes, undercutting the argument from selection pressure advanced here?

      Initially, surely yes. But not for long, even assuming [implausibly] that the world's poorest nations will remain poor indefinitely. Consider how rapidly web-enabled cell phones have spread through even impoverished sub-Saharan Africa. If personal genome sequencing always costs anything like the $200,000 it does now [December 2008; year 2013 = c.$10,000], then only an elite of affluent Westerners could benefit from such breakthroughs. If personal genome sequencing cost ten dollars or less, then effectively everyone can have it. The nature of information and information technology entails that IT-based services don't involve the consumption of scarce natural resources in the way material goods do, where one person's gain is frequently another person's loss. Only a handful of people in the world can ever own a Rolls Royce or a Maserati, and even fewer can own an original Picasso or an Old Master; but an unlimited number of people can listen to the world's entire catalogue of music, enjoy access to all its electronic games, its computer software, its movies, or indeed the whole Library of Congress. Information is effectively free, or at least it will be soon. Later this century, reproductive technologies like preimplantation genetic screening (PGS) and diagnosis (PGD) - techniques used to identify genetic defects in embryos created through in vitro fertilization before pregnancy - are going to become dirt-cheap too. Already crude personal genotyping services are available for a few hundred dollars.

      Of course it's easy to sing a happy tune with the word "soon". I'm glossing over a host of problems in the transitional era between old-fashioned sexual reproduction and true planned parenthood. "Soon" in this context may mean decades, and perhaps centuries. But even on the most conservative timescales, we're on the brink of a major discontinuity in the four-billion-year odyssey of the evolution of life on Earth.

      Some Unknowns

      Human Cloning.
      One big unknown affecting any conjectures about future selection pressure is the role of human cloning. Whether human reproductive cloning takes another five years or fifty years, it is going to happen. What's less clear is the cost and expertise involved when the technology matures, and what are its global implications for selection pressure. If human cloning will always take a large team of research professionals, complex medical equipment, many failed attempts and a great deal of money, then it will presumably always be rare. But if it can ever be done cheaply and safely at home, perhaps via DIY cloning kits available for purchase over the Net, then human cloning could become a common way to make babies, regardless of official laws and regulations.

      For the sake of argument, let's suppose that human cloning does eventually become a common mode of reproduction. It's not clear this is a bad development per se, any more than identical twins or triplets are intrinsically bad. Either way, this possibility might seem to throw a big spanner into the argument from selection pressure I'm making here, since genetically identical babies are likely to suffer from the same problems as their father or mother if exposed to a similar environment.

      Yet it seems a reasonable assumption that most future human cloners won't seek to create exact genetic duplicates of themselves, but will instead aspire to have offspring free of defects or unwanted characteristics possessed by their parent. To use a trivial example, a human cloner with thinning hair wouldn't necessarily want to have a cloned child with a predisposition to grow bald. Granted, most Asian people who want a clone will want to have children who are Asian-looking, and most blue-eyed people will probably want blue-eyed clones, but presumably carriers of the cystic fibrosis allele won't seek to pass the defective gene on to their cloned offspring. Likewise, for the most part depressive people who might like to clone themselves aren't likely to want depressive children. Cases of "negative enhancement", akin to the existing use of preimplantation genetic diagnosis to select an embryo for the presence of a particular disability such as deafness shared by the parent(s), will presumably be uncommon. So yes, if human cloning becomes widespread, and certainly if human cloning becomes cheap and ubiquitous, then its spread makes the argument from selection pressure defended here more complex; but the practice wouldn't fundamentally undercut its conclusion.

      Autosomal Gene Therapy and Enhancement.
      Another unknown that adds to the complexity of the selection pressure argument is the future extent of autosomal gene therapy. I've been focusing on reproduction and germ-line gene therapy and genetic enhancement; but somatic gene therapy is sure to become available and probably extensively used too. After all, if offered the choice of either taking a drug to remedy some physical or psychological defect for the rest of your life or curing that deficit with a one-off course of gene therapy, which would you choose - if you were sure that the gene therapy was safe and effective? The same is true of future enhancement technologies - though remediation versus enhancement is a naïve dichotomy.

      Potential Pitfalls

      The Spectre of Coercive Eugenics.
      Anyone uncritically enthusiastic about the Reproductive Revolution in prospect would do well to reflect on the history of the twentieth century. In the words of bioethicist Nicholas Agar, "Those who do not learn from the history of human enhancement may be doomed to repeat it". One recalls the forced segregation, sterilization, racial hygiene, the euthanasia program and ultimately the genocide practised in the pseudo-scientific name of eugenics. Might the impending Reproductive Revolution lead to similar horrors? After all, there are still plenty of people in the world convinced that some races are intellectually or morally superior to other races. Might history repeat itself?

      The short answer is yes, though I think such scenarios are unlikely. For a start, the totalitarian dictatorships of the twentieth century, not least the Third Reich, all depended on censorship and a state-monopoly of information. The Internet makes the creation of totalitarian dictatorships much harder; as has been well said, the Internet interprets censorship as damage and re-routes. However, this is obviously a huge topic. All I'll say here is that there is a fundamental difference between a regulatory system where eugenics [under whatever name] is practised for the well-being of the individual - whether human or non-human - and an authoritarian society where eugenics is practised for the notional benefit of a class, race or nation.

      Even so, there are clearly lots of problems with so-called liberal eugenics. For instance, there are pitfalls with prospective parents choosing enhancements that offer a merely positional advantage to their children. To give a concrete example, if parents pick genes likely to allow their child to grow taller than current average, then there is no net benefit to either the child or society if most other parents do the same. Indeed if human stature were to become significantly higher than today, then we would all be prone to multiple health difficulties under Earth's gravitational regime. Even enhancements such as genes that may contribute to superior intelligence - overexpressing or adding extra copies of the NRP2 or ASPM or microcephalin gene to use a contentious example - that sound as though they could confer intrinsic benefit might arguably amount to positional goods like height. Thus women tend to find intelligence sexy in prospective mates; but presumably what's advantageous to the brainy male bearer in terms of enhanced sex-appeal is relative- and not absolute- intelligence. A counter to this argument might be that there are inherent benefits to high male intelligence aside from attracting women.

      In contrast with interventions that confer positional advantage, genetic enhancements that enrich subjective well-being - crudely, whether you are temperamentally happy or superhappy - would be intrinsically beneficial; they can potentially benefit everyone, regardless of where one falls on any comparative scale of well-being. Indeed technologies that biologically enrich emotional well-being are arguably the only enhancements that are intrinsically good as distinct from positionally or instrumentally good. This claim is obviously controversial; it would be contested by many bioethicists who aren't classical utilitarians.

      Other pitfalls?
      Although designer genomes can in principle lead to vastly greater diversity, might designer genomes lead in practice to greater genetic uniformity - if most parents strive to have similar kinds of "ideal" children, the supernormal reflections of preferences adaptive in our Darwinian past? Admittedly, some kinds of genetic uniformity are presumably desirable. Thus by common consent it would be a blessing if there were no gene for Huntington's disease (HD). But twentieth century eugenicists didn't take account of phenomena such as heterozygote advantage - normally defined as cases where the heterozygote genotype has a higher relative fitness than either the homozygote dominant or homozygote recessive genotype. Heterozygote advantage explains why some kinds of genetic variability persist, most famously the gene for sickle-cell anaemia. Analogous heterozygote advantage may exist for psychological traits too, though this is unproven.

      Whatever their evolutionary origin, here are three examples where the issues are complicated.

      The Future of Homosexuality: Even if you have absolutely no prejudices at all about homosexuality, would you choose so-called gay genes for your child - variant alleles that predispose your child to be gay? Now of course it's possible that in 50 or 150 years time, homophobia will have been relegated to the dustbin of history where it belongs; but I wouldn't count on it. In the meantime, what percentage of prospective parents, whether straight or gay or bisexual, will deliberately choose to have a gay child knowing the greater social problems that child would be likely to encounter in life due to social prejudice? If this is the case, and if there is indeed a Reproductive Revolution as outlined here, then it is quite likely that genes predisposing to homosexuality and possibly even bisexuality will be strongly selected against. They may even die out. If one looks in human history from classical antiquity to the present at the contribution made by people whom we would probably classify as gay or bisexual, and likewise at the contribution of their close genetic relatives, then this is not an outcome to be contemplated lightly. On the other hand, it's also possible that many gay couples will use the new reproductive technologies to have gay children, rendering the gay extinction scenario moot.

      The Future of Bipolar Disorder: Chronic unipolar depression may be an unmitigated evil; but what about Bipolar Disorder, formerly known as manic depression? Bipolar Disorder can undoubtedly cause terrible suffering both to its victims and their families. Yet many creative high achievers in art, science and politics have at the very least been soft bipolars. Is there a danger that something valuable will be lost if in future prospective parents weed out of the gene-pool alleles associated with bipolarity? Again, this is a huge topic.

      The Future of Autism Spectrum Disorders: Classical autism is characterized by varying degrees of "mindblindness" and deficits in social interaction; deficits in language, communication, and the capacity for social play; and multiple stereotypies of behaviour. The three most common forms of autism spectrum disorders (ASD) are classical autism; pervasive developmental disorder not otherwise specified (PDD-NOS); and Asperger's syndrome. Whereas children with, say, trisomy 21 (Down syndrome) or Williams syndrome can be abnormally sociable - and therefore rewarding to raise - by contrast autistic children with an absent or underdeveloped theory of mind commonly cause great distress to their caregivers. It is hard to bond with someone who always treats you as an object. Thus any genetic disposition to autism might seem a prime candidate for elimination from the gene-pool as the Reproductive Revolution gathers pace. However, some of the greatest scientists who ever lived, notably Newton, Einstein and Dirac, fulfill many or all of the diagnostic criteria for Asperger's syndrome. To what extent was their scientific acumen separable from their pathologies of mind?

      Calculating Risk-Reward Ratios

      If there are likely to be so many possible adverse and/or unintended consequences of the new reproductive medicine - and perhaps dystopian outcomes no one has even considered - then why forge ahead? Why not outlaw the new reproductive technologies altogether, or at least drastically restrict their use to simple Mendelian genetic diseases of the body rather than complex disorders of the mind/brain? After all, there is no way we can computationally model all the ramifications of even modest rewrites of the human genome.

      Here the question comes down to an analysis of risk-reward ratios - and our basic ethical values, themselves shaped by our evolutionary past. Lest extension of the new reproductive medicine seem too rashly experimental even to contemplate, it's worth recalling that each act of old-fashioned sexual reproduction is itself an untested genetic experiment, the outcome of random mutations and meiotic shuffling of the genetic deck, and with no happy ending to date. So just who are we to accuse of reckless gambling? As it stands, all of us are genetically predestined to grow old and die; and in the course of a lifetime, the great majority of humans will experience periods of intense psychological distress, for instance loneliness and heartache after an unhappy love affair. Our social primate biology ensures that most of us sometimes experience, to a greater or lesser degree, all manner of nasty states that were genetically adaptive in the ancestral environment e.g. jealousy, resentment, anger, and so forth. Hundreds of millions of people in the world today suffer bouts of depression; others live with chronic anxiety. One might say these phenotypes are part of what it means to be human. Worse, we pass a heritable predisposition to these horrible states on to our children.

      Bioconservatives, religious traditionalists, and social reformers alike would contest this bleak analysis. If you believe that human life today is fundamentally good, and viciously unpleasant states of mind are an aberration that can be mostly remedied by improving society, then you will need compelling reasons before wanting to change the regime of ordinary sexual reproduction as it exists now. Most likely, you will be loathe to support anything like the Reproductive Revolution predicted here; and focus entirely on its potential dangers. The spectre of "Brave New World" will probably loom large in any discussion. If, on the other hand, you think that Darwinian life is cruel and tragic by its very nature, then you are more likely to be willing to contemplate radical alternatives to the genetic status quo, despite the possible risks.

      My own view of the risks and uncertainties is that there is a critical distinction between trying to abolish suffering exclusively via social reform and abolishing suffering directly via biotechnology. As we know, utopian social experiments typically go wrong, sometimes hideously wrong, and end up causing a lot of suffering instead. The abolitionist project of eradicating the biological substrates of suffering sounds like just another utopian scheme, whether it's touted as a grandiose species-project or simply as a byproduct of the Reproductive Revolution explored here. Although the abolition of psychological pain is arguably no more utopian in principle than pain-free surgery, it could presumably go wrong in unanticipated ways too. Perhaps we'll unwittingly create a fool's paradise. But if and when we ever abolish the molecular underpinning of unpleasant experience, and it becomes physiologically impossible for any sentient being to suffer, we thereby change the very meaning of what it is for anything to "go wrong". Unwelcome surprises where no one gets hurt are very different from unwelcome surprises where they do. For what it's worth, I think the abolition of involuntary suffering is the precondition of any civilised posthuman society; and therefore a risk worth taking.

      The End of Sexual Reproduction?

      OK, I've outlined grounds for believing that our nastier Darwinian emotions will be selected against in future. Yet there is a fundamental objection to the argument from selection pressure that I've sketched so far. Surely most people, not least teenagers, will carry on producing babies by having sex together regardless of any so-called Reproductive Revolution of laboratory-mediated conception. Unplanned pregnancies are extremely common even in an age where contraceptives are widely available. Yes, maybe responsible, forward-looking parents will seek to ensure that they have children who are free of genetic handicaps, who are joyful, ultra-intelligent, super-empathetic and psychologically robust; and maybe in future such responsible parents-to-be will practise preimplantation genetic diagnosis, use germline gene therapy and pursue some of the futuristic interventions described here. But that won't stop feckless teenagers having unplanned babies. In addition, billions of people may be reluctant to embrace the new reproductive technologies for traditional moral or religious reasons, or simply out of custom and habit. It stretches the imagination to envisage genetically planned parenthood ever becoming as prevalent as, say, anaesthetics to guarantee pain-free surgery. If most fertile women continue to bear genetically unenriched babies by the conventional route, then surely our inbuilt genetic tendency to all forms of Darwinian suffering is going to express itself indefinitely?

      Maybe so. It's a powerful argument. Yet there are strong grounds for thinking that traditional-style sexual reproduction can't continue for more than a few generations. The reason is bound up with the coming revolution in antiaging medicine.

      Throughout most of human history, radical life-extension, let alone the prospect of eternal youth, has been the province of quacks and charlatans. To some extent it still is; swallowing a bunch of vitamin pills each day isn't going to let you live for ever. But over the next few centuries, and possibly before, aging and the genes that promote or allow senescence are going be phased out. This is of course a bold claim that I won't even attempt to defend in detail here. If you are sceptical and haven't read the book already, I'd recommend Aubrey de Grey's Ending Aging: The Rejuvenation Breakthroughs That Could Reverse Human Aging in Our Lifetime (2007). Now I am more pessimistic than Aubrey de Grey about timescales. Yet the genetic and pharmacological interventions that we are already trying in nonhuman animals will eventually be tried in the human animal too. One hesitates to embrace what sounds like a facile technological determinism; but I think we can say, quite dogmatically, that if and when radical antiaging technologies become available, then the overwhelming majority of people will use them - regardless of any rationalizations of death and aging we express now. Moreover most people will also want such treatments for their family pets; the Antiaging Revolution won't be confined to one species.

      Let's assume for the sake of argument that this is the case i.e. there will be both a Reproductive Revolution and an Antiaging Revolution. If post-genomic medicine dramatically extends lifespan, and fewer and fewer people die of the traditional diseases of old age, then our planet will soon reach its carrying capacity. Looking centuries ahead, a rapidly expanding population of eternally youthful quasi-immortals means that human reproduction of any kind will have to become rare, and eventually a momentous event, and tightly controlled in every respect. It's here that I foresee both the greatest ethical dilemmas arising from the Reproductive Revolution and also the intimate link between superhappiness, superintelligence and superlongevity.

      Selection Pressure in an Age of Quasi-Immortality

      When the Earth reaches its carrying capacity - the maximum packing density of sentient beings consistent with sustainable life - there will have to be immensely greater centralized control of the human reproductive system on pain of complete Malthusian catastrophe. This does indeed sound a truly sinister prediction. Perhaps one can imagine the existence of a mandatory regime of depot-contraception from an early age. Yet could depot-contraception really be made fail-safe? How would such fertility control be enforced? Moreover the problem isn't just preventing reproductive accidents. The urge to have one's "own" children can be extraordinarily strong, as attested by the anguish caused by involuntary childlessness today; and for many childless couples, this yearning could eclipse any general worries about the carrying capacity of the planet. A majority of people will want both to stay forever young and to have children. If radical antiaging technologies are indeed widely adopted, then a central and unavoidably intrusive control of human reproduction may be inevitable, though one may trust such powers will be accountable to democratic control. In an era of mass superlongevity, every intellectually competent citizen will presumably recognize, in the abstract, that unlimited free reproduction is physically impossible. On the other hand, some people will presumably try to have unregulated, unsanctioned children, just as they do in the People's Republic of China (PRC) today, albeit without the promise of eternal youth. This is not an attractive parallel. Of course there are other social perils associated with mass superlongevity: in an era of genetically pre-programmed eternal youth, the ruling power elites may prove almost immovable in the absence of adequate democratic safeguards. But the potential loss of bodily autonomy and procreative liberty is especially troubling to the liberal conscience - and to any libertarian life-extensionist.

      A counterargument here is that the urge to bear children is under genetic control; and that urge will itself be amenable to biological intervention. Manipulation of our first-order desires is likely to prove biologically easier than defeating aging. Yet if most of one's enhanced fellow citizens do act responsibly and forgo or postpone reproduction, then any predisposition to "cheat" and have children might be highly (genetically) adaptive, at least in the short-run. Such an outcome would be disastrous in an already overpopulated global megalopolis. Plausible group selectionist scenarios aren't easy to construct even for the far future. Hence the price of posthuman superlongevity is the likelihood of ever greater state intervention in the (hitherto) private realm - although such intrusiveness need not be subjectively distressing in any sense we would recognise today, since the functional analogue of distress might suffice. Long before any era of post-genomic medicine, Plato believed that human reproduction should be monitored and controlled by the state, a portent of totalitarian societies to come; but once we transcend the biology of human mortality, some sort of collective control of reproductive decision-making may prove inescapable even in a liberal democracy. The only alternative to such control would be draconian, state-enforced rationing of anti-aging therapies: a scarcely credible re-enactment of Logan's Run. It's important to note that this argument doesn't turn on whether it transpires that the ultimate carrying capacity of our planet is 15 billion, or 150 billion, or conceivably even higher packing densities. Yes, we can colonise the Solar System. In theory, too, in some era of the distant future, the authorities on Earth could tell anyone who wants to have a child that they must do so on one of the extrasolar planetary systems that we colonise. But for the next few centuries at least, and possibly millennia, the prospect of some kind of Galactic adaptive radiation is pure science-fiction. For it is hard to overstate the technical obstacles to mass interstellar travel. Quite possibly posthumans will go to the stars, and perhaps even colonise our local galactic supercluster in a few million years or so. Realistically, this doesn't solve the near-term demographic challenge of a massively overcrowded Earth.

      Admittedly I am making a number of contestable assumptions here. I will note just three. First, intelligent life won't wipe itself out altogether in the next few decades. [Doomsday scenarios are conceivable; but they are much harder to construct once self-sustaining colonies are established on other planets later this century.] Second, there is a unique past and a unique future. [This simplifying assumption is inconsistent with quantum cosmology and most likely false. However, consideration of the "branch density” measure of alternative, classically inequivalent histories in post-Everett quantum mechanics would take us too far afield in this talk.] Third, unlike futurists who believe in "uploading", I am assuming that our (post)human descendants will retain an organic substrate - maybe augmented by web-enabled neurochips, nanobots, bionic implants and the like - and hence that humans won't scan, digitize and "upload" themselves to dwell in another computational medium where the constraints of the Earth's ecosystem don't apply. [There is no evidence that your PC is any more conscious than an abacus, despite its greater processing power; and if a souped-up version of your PC contained a digitized representation of you, this would doubtless facilitate restoration from backups, but there are no grounds for thinking such lines of code would be conscious either - let alone "you". Yes, artificial intelligence will hasten the Reproductive Revolution; and perhaps one day we will all become web-enabled cyborgs. And who knows what kinds of exotic postbiological artificial life can be evolved if and when our descendants run mature quantum computers. Yet there is simply no evidence that inorganic systems with a classical von Neumann architecture support "raw feels" or intrinsically matter: the notion that our species might destructively upload ourselves from basement Reality into digital nirvana is unworkable.] So here at least I am being tamely bioconservative in assuming that the Earth 1000 years hence will support a densely populated primordial "meatworld" of our flesh-and-blood post-human descendants.

      Anyhow, to summarise, assume that the creation of new quasi-immortal beings will indeed become exceedingly rare later this millennium. The Earth will be (almost) literally full. I'd argue that on such historic occasions as the creation of a new posthuman-being, it is unlikely that superhappy, superintelligent agents will create the genetic malware for unpleasant, stupid, senile substrates of consciousness i.e. archaic Homo sapiens. Our posthuman descendants are more likely to create fellow "smart angels" instead. The triumph of the Reproductive Revolution will have reshaped the post-Darwinian fitness landscape beyond all recognition. Hence my (tentative) prediction that the biology of suffering and senescence is destined to pass into evolutionary history.

      David Pearce, 2009
      La revolución reproductiva (Spanish tr.)
      Die reproduktive Revolution (German tr.)

      See also Liberal Eugenics?
      The Biointelligence Explosion (2012)


      The Abolitionist Project
      Refs
      and further reading

      Resources
      Talks 2015
      Eugenics.org
      BLTC Research
      Liberal Eugenics
      Superhappiness?
      Utopian Surgery?
      The End of Suffering
      Wirehead Hedonism
      Social Media (2023)
      The Good Drug Guide
      Paradise Engineering
      The Abolitionist Project
      Quora Answers (2015-23)
      The Hedonistic Imperative
      The Biointelligence Explosion
      MDMA: Utopian Pharmacology
      Full-Spectrum Superintelligence
      ChatGPT on the Reproductive Revolution
      The World Transhumanist Organization/H+
      Critique of Aldous Huxley's Brave New World
      Selection Pressure in a Post-Darwinian World (2): Gene Drives (2016)

      e-mail
      dave@hedweb.com

      "'I'll make old vases for you if you want them—will make them just as I made these.' He had visions of a room full of golden brown beard. It was the most appalling thing he had ever witnessed, and there was no trickery about it. The beard had actually grown before his eyes, and it had now reached to the second button of the Clockwork man's waistcoat. And, at any moment, Mrs. Masters might return! "Worth stealing," a Society journalist lounging by remarked. "I could write a novel, only I can never think of a plot. Your old housekeeper is asleep long ago. Where do you carry your latchkey?" "Never lose your temper," he said. "It leads to apoplexy. Ah, my fine madam, you thought to pinch me, but I have pinched you instead." How does that strike you, Mr. Smith? Fancy Jerusha Abbott, (individually) ever pat me on the head, Daddy? I don't believe so-- The confusion was partly inherited from Aristotle. When discussing the psychology of that philosopher, we showed that his active Nous is no other than the idea of which we are at any moment actually conscious. Our own reason is the passive Nous, whose identity is lost in the multiplicity of objects with which it becomes identified in turn. But Aristotle was careful not to let the personality of God, or the supreme Nous, be endangered by resolving it into the totality of substantial forms which constitute Nature. God is self-conscious in the strictest sense. He thinks nothing but himself. Again, the subjective starting-point of305 Plotinus may have affected his conception of the universal Nous. A single individual may isolate himself from his fellows in so far as he is a sentient being; he cannot do so in so far as he is a rational being. His reason always addresses itself to the reason of some one else—a fact nowhere brought out so clearly as in the dialectic philosophy of Socrates and Plato. Then, when an agreement has been established, their minds, before so sharply divided, seem to be, after all, only different personifications of the same universal spirit. Hence reason, no less than its objects, comes to be conceived as both many and one. And this synthesis of contradictories meets us in modern German as well as in ancient Greek philosophy. 216 "I shall be mighty glad when we git this outfit to Chattanoogy," sighed Si. "I'm gittin' older every minute that I have 'em on my hands." "What was his name?" inquired Monty Scruggs. "Wot's worth while?" "Rose, Rose—my dear, my liddle dear—you d?an't mean——" "I'm out of practice, or I shouldn't have skinned myself like this—ah, here's Coalbran's trap. Perhaps he'll give you a lift, ma'am, into Peasmarsh." Chapter 18 "The Fair-pl?ace." "Yes," replied Black Jack, "here they are," drawing a parchment from his pocket. "This is the handwriting of a retainer called Oakley." HoME大桥未久AV手机在线观看 ENTER NUMBET 0016www.kailong.net.cn
      www.ifsrin.com.cn
      www.silk-ev.com.cn
      www.shxmpt.com.cn
      www.wangpiying.com.cn
      qz7.com.cn
      nmgqzgwy.com.cn
      www.wschain.com.cn
      xdchain.com.cn
      gebangni.com.cn
      丝袜美腿恋足和脚交全部成人电影电驴下载 簧色图片狠簧狠狠秃噜 美熟母快播电影网 伊斯兰国妇女性交电影 少妇喜欢被操吗 留守熟娘自拍 国产全裸写真下载地址 操逼小说之母女 波多野结衣专辑 淫乱家庭日 另类图片天天 oumeisetuhahasedouhang 欧美丝袜厕所脚 学生妹内射图 WWW_68ABAB_COM 大奶裸体美乳 此影片受美国法律堡在线 日本爱视频 少爷 雏 开苞 偷拍孕妇的乳房 第一部家庭淫乱史 mgscl55 avsiwa 最新免费艺术片 俩性与爱图删除 bt 欧美 肛交 小77婷婷五月天 淫荡的少妇快播 男人狂插女人狂叫 屄【p】 陈静仪乳头很大吗 西西人体穴 qiangjianxiaoyima 藤井蕾娜 欧美乱伦交 狠狠抠女人 五月天逼逼图片 美女写真有哪些 丝袜漏在线播放 骚女浪妇乱伦爱爱 张芳人体艺术摄影 成人女孩网 台湾插18人体艺术图 高清无码人体艺术的网站 男女同事肏屄的小说 丁香熟女少妇乱伦图 浙江真实乱伦迅雷 天空中出的170cm电梯小姐种子 母子父女操逼乱伦小说或偷拍 美国十次啦毛片 淫荡二嫂 熟女人人妻18p 国产十大美女3在线播放 南京师范大学菁林园 尾行3打不开 裸体照下面带毛 导航少妇 哥哥就要操 父女交欢 女性人体黄照视频 zhan昭艳谈 羽田爱影音先锋 女人阴道屁毛裸体全身照片一一 狂草美人3p 日屄性爱激情 wohelilaoshixingjiao 女人外阴实物图真人 d人体艺术网 母子交合怀孕的小说 辰溪四中艳照门照片 国外男性美图 姨妈美丽和乱伦 模特羽田人体 古色古香 丁字裤小穴 亚洲图片欧美图片色妹妹 我爱仓井空 自拍亚洲欧美迅雷下载电驴下载 国产偷拍论坛下载 史上最大性器bt 14岁屁眼 dzu7788 日本做爱刑片 欧美超性感高跟丝袜艳舞 紫涵影音先锋av 世界操骚逼新闻 操熊黛林小说 欧美黑丝老师做爱 和妈妈一家做爱 中国女人屄屄图片 黑人干美女的的电影 韩国大奶少妇诱惑图 乱伦少妇系列小说 日本人体艺术乳秀 德国黄色片男女偷情同性恋强奸 我和妈妈 91tv影院软件下载 WWW55ABCDECOM 印尼屠华qvod 少妇大胆鲍鱼激情成人小说快播 黑丝网妇在线 谁有在线看g片网站 WWW520MSNCOM 哥哥舔我文 零久少女秘宝馆成人套图 凌辱丝袜美女 国内莫航空公司空姐性爱视频合集影音先锋 三级片免费在线网站 西西人体葵司 曹颖欧美丰满女人大逼人体艺术 家庭乱伦97ai 天天干夜撸 幼女13岁女睡后毛才五六根rmbttd 日本无码qvod 小明看看平台se7se7 国产自拍少妇内射在线 肉色丝袜脚超清 兽交网址很插美女穴亚洲色 近亲相奸影院 老婆怀孕我和岳母做爱 身上光溜溜的女人图片 女人阴口是屁股眼吗 弟弟插妹妹的故事 搜库曹查理 欧美大胆写真种子视频 911sss911s 色狼漫画人鱼 黑丝高跟影速先锋 五月天激情网迅雷下载 12岁女孩逼什么样 欧洲美女冶剖悠 熟女无料h动画 骚穴yang 母亲儿子做爱乱伦电影 涩皮娘子滑皮官 丰满大白屁股 衅夹大逼松 欧美性爱高清快播 日韩近亲先锋影音 琪琪影院经典片 亚洲少女操逼图 色干女 处女第一次性交视频合集 妻子让朋友干出尿 莫色一片段 强奸萝莉的h小说 wwwzxulicom 亚洲色图p伊人 山村母女抽B 最新国产自拍高潮合集迅雷 bbS师城网影视大全大全性交 捆绑美女老师 和妈妈的乱伦性爱小说岳母 hentai天天酷跑 新新电影理论人妻 qyuletv青娱乐在线 丰满大屁股嫂子 影音先锋ady三级片 setu22进入中 阿姨叫从后面进入 av动画优优色影院 亚洲色图久草网偷拍自拍视频 ww51zhaofupo官网 短篇黄书txt下载 开女儿嫩苞的小说 空天使亚洲色图 吹箫三级片古代 ppt播放avi黑屏 留学生性爱偷拍视频 武侠古典潘金莲 大陆色屌操 duopapadiz 牛d叉电影伦理电影 搜索www人与兽交 黄色电影三级片老毛女 大奶妹激吻动态图 sese尤物 亚洲强奸丝袜文章 舔B乳头 三级网络地址直接免费五月天 那个文字magnet kp快播成人版 av色老太老头 美女AV视频xw970com 老师干儿子淫秽 成人流氓视频下载 春药火腿肠 网友ed2k 美女图片的逼逼屁屁前边 超碰淫淫网 gan38comwwwgzyunhecom 农夫色资源 SM真实自拍 邻家阿姨叫我添她下面 激情五夜四射 八戒街拍裙底 wwwluotinuren 亚洲色图网站激情套图 阜阳GAY 人妻淫淫网 久久外国三级视频 吖吖色资源吧 纵犬潜伏讯雷 明星淫乱狠狠 东方在线出行 久久电影网wwwdy99cn b33mmminfo 日本人与狗种子 亚洲电影二区 大黑逼25 huangse淫淫wang 大胆人体摸特乱轮小说 三级片最狠的是什么 免费淫图 张筱雨人体身影下载 苍井空操逼时候视频 巨乳的诱惑电影 sao妹妹电影 我为明日花死 AV制服丝袜 13yn_com 公交车上被啊啊啊好爽 俺去也先锋小说 海贼王色色视频手机在线观看 CADV480 幼激情社区 影音先锋淫荡人妻 av大帝骚色在线视频 A片性交电影 四虎影库必出精品浅仓彩音 ooxx名侦探柯南 色春阁熟女18p 成人王网站 最新激情图片 欧美sm暴力虐待女图片 自拍av射射 免XX网址 欧美性爱偷拍自拍图片 女人下部真实图片 三级a片在线 动漫女生的恶搞图片 9sekecim 色艳片 一群女人靠逼 幼幼导航最干净的 淫媳荡翁的性生活爱爱 偷拍自拍第1页大香蕉 日日撸成人 老师夹得我好紧 国内自拍强奸乱伦 www4d4d4dm 一本美女性交生活 2017最新流出视频种子 青青草影院 熟女诱惑微拍 日韩制服丝片 亚洲色视频无码专区 gv视频在线免费观看 做爱鸡巴疼怎么办啊 姐妹监禁教师 父女乱伦视频网站 小纯洁777在线影院 影音先锋欧美性爱AV 人体艺术野战 琪琪网站色猫网 t多毛中文学院视频 日妣漫画 下载激 Hh网 蝌蚪窝vr pin6biz 淘宝团购 人人操色8 anquse 捆绑强奸娇喘视频 偷窥自拍欧美色图在线播放 成人电影快播影院 色老网 Kjfulic0m bt种子下载成人无码 人体艺术偷拍另类 亚洲色图区大色小色 wwwf4yycon 幼10P 偷拍自拍另类贴图 3344nq zz1818 htppwwwbbbvodcom haodiaoorg的综合查询 062bcomwap231dycom 少妇诱惑舞蹈 西西国模 JQWY5COM 淫浪网 就爱草逼逼 在线观看田中美佐野战 adyavz r3影院 亚裔成人色图 52av若怒 gegean 触手录官网 阿片吧 萝莉另类小说 wwwxxx美少女 豆豆rrcom 在线AV偷拍视频 草榴掰阴偷拍自拍 人体艺术秀美女贴图 日本大奶老熟女肥阴 金发天国在线播放1 狠狠撸不需下载播放器的av片 刘亦菲不雅动态图 动漫av迅雷下载 免费手机av皇帝 偷拍自拍野外母子做爱 iuo体图片美女gu乳房 色和尚香蕉撸 性爱技巧校园春色小说 WWW_H222_COMHWWW 啊啊啊av 爱幼幼社区 mkkavtv 音影先锋大香蕉伊人 第九影院第一页 99re6久久热在线观看3 肉体ys 日本猜人游戏在线影院 黑丝袜的逼 美国小孩性交配 wwwrrrfffcom 9977玖玖 范冰冰狠狠撸种子 3wbbbcom 网yiny 男人吃女人的乳房好吗 人妻好吊视频在线观看 色在线奶奶 8vaa褋芯屑 七七电影第一页 snn妻妻彬 MXGS673 粉嫩人体美穴 网吧嗯啊 天天撸撸丁香 88街拍视频网 欧美小萝莉6080 快播伦理艺术 第二色激情 av一本道视频在线观看 尼姑福利网 www路993bb路com 偷拍自拍新疆妹子 偷拍自拍福利都市 另类小说迅雷专区 给老婆找鸭子magnet 超碰yjizztv 手机在线你懂的免费 厕沟间谍spychinaclu 922bbb966bbb肛交 丰满骚妇淫叫 wwwky757com为什么看不了 44kkmmtvcom 久久精品在线5 性虐黄色电影 五月天色哥哥色妹妹 狠狠干狠狠做狠狠爱 一本道无玛avwwwvid11comwwwvid11com 日本金山升一在线视频 求在线能看黄色的网站 久久色女儿阁 国模大胆阴部 国产操逼A片 亚洲无码凸凹视频 黄色视频啪啪啪网站在线观看 黄色艺术乱论故事 强奸乱伦8爱色电影院 打飞机时看的裸照 国模图片小说三级图片 插B十V是啥意思 中国老奶奶的毛wwwredtubecom 伦理偷拍自拍人妻少妇 林志玲rentiyishu 新疆男人鸡吧图片 九九热翘臀 在线播放波多野结衣A级视频 www295555ocm 醉地撸成人免费av视频 412vvcom 干了五个美女的小屁眼 男人资源高清无码 美女人体艺术pp胸 偷拍大学生美术课上裸体写真图 蔡美玲 ed2k 快播成人之美连续剧 日本中学生乳艺术 李宗瑞迷奸门快播全集 操嫂嫂b文章 eva美女邪恶漫画 撸师妹亚洲色图 和邻居姐姐做爱 小说我和小姨性生活 大鸡吧色图 求东京热网盘mp4 濑穴 骚女有种子 绑起来干33p 肥女人体艺照 国模林娜 913p 无美美鲍人体艺术 国外幼幼乱伦电影 泰国佬猛插日本性娘3p大战 丝袜 熟女 欧美 韩国性感美女操逼视频 国模杜箐箐私处 WWW_DUOTE_COMTECHK 欧美成人激情综合 熟妇口交照片 爱爱谷商城射黑丝袜 大鸡巴日大奶美女骚屄图片 日本人体七艺术 先锋成人乱伦强暴网址 国产操少妇 父女性爱母子性交 av 色 苍井空搞一次多少钱 日本无码电影qvod 好莱坞女星照片泄漏下载百度云 wo de laoshishi 骚逼 小77乱伦图片 激情日本人体艺术 女生 肥逼大奶老妇女全祼激情图 45chengren d9e4590e0000131d 黑木明纱无码快播 美国美女十次啦 曰本艺术图片 男女真人噪b写真 就去写真 看明星簧片的 亿性家自拍偷拍视频 自拍偷拍激情艳照 小乳房嫩比美女 乱搞性爱生活 扶苏 狱锁狂龙5 李宗瑞视频在那 激情亚洲色妹妹奇米 好色妻降临美兰惠子 美国人家庭性爱乱伦春暖花开 我爱插逼网色图 美女与黑人操逼图贴 daruoxue 美女性爱过程图 白洁骚屄有声小说 黑黑色成人免费视频 伊一人体合成图 电影明星操逼 超级人体艺术p10 黄色电子书色播 谁有少妇图片 xxx4tubetv 痷去也图区 奈香里子 莎丽人体 波多野结衣美图作品集 哥哥AV网视 丝袜骚妇人妻乱伦 亚州色图27p 欧美丝袜就去色色 渡涞晶人体艺术 强奸在线成人视频 丝袜播放器 韩国美人图未来影院神马电影 教师操屄 明被迷奸 苍井空qvod电影在线 天天激综合总站 色男色女3级片 射人阁我要爱爱网站 看电影来5566有闲夫人 f05bbd3e00007510 超嫩10岁妹子嫩穴嫩肉嫩奶子 ah442百度影院 体恐惧内射玉i农民精过2 人体艺体祼体 午夜影院播放版破解版下载 RE789COM mp3黄片一级 torrent日本av 欧美性爱大图色图强奸乱 h小游戏口交 网友自拍草榴裙社区 无码动画大全 激情3p图 苍井空爆操女人前后 逍遥社区淫淫就去色色 爱爱美少女成人网 WWW34SPZCOM 幼幼资源影音先锋 女人的阴毛无马赛克 WWWXINAISHEDESCOM 男同番号 中文sexxxx 影音先锋可播的成人动漫 大胆高清美女人体艺术图片图 色图色噜 动态男女性交图片 老年夫妻操逼视频 激情网站wwwhuangsedianyingnet luluhei网站最新地址 久操视频偷拍 亚洲图片欧美偷拍o 乱乱色图 淫欲女秘书在线观看 狐狸精导航 卡通动漫欧美日本 嫖娼影音先锋资源 性交动攸 Av天天操 黄色舔逼逼小说 摸骚妇宾馆 肛交av网站 被轮奸的感觉真爽 mmp4ppC0m 好屌色公开视觉 大香蕉网人人摸 户外露出的网站 奇奇热奇奇色妻子撸 大学生情趣网袜 guaishou521 干干爽 亚洲是图p1百度臊妇淫荡图片 手机Avzx 青青草www99kk496cn 久久在线视频精品99re6mweibocn 操逼的牛牛 黄色特级aaaaa片 激情女同小说另类 欧洲人做太国在线Av 胖哥人体艺术 赵东赫 插妹妹黄色网站 美女口交舔逼小说 久久幼女孩色视频 成人黄色电影国产片 欧美激情淫荡熟妇 88tv熟女人妻 小色网视频女友想要 123首播伦理影院 爱人人体艺术摄影裸体照 少妇的qq或微信 影音资源激情小说家庭乱伦 出租车抠逼 流出淫水 2017搜片神器是那个 气密四色 调教奸肉棒性奴 快播热女人妻小说 青青草少女学生 少妇自拍偷拍在线111kk 色天使在钱 亚洲色图欧美另类校园春色 爱撸吧tumblr 四房播播丁香区 九九版国产黑人操免费视频 北岛玲操逼图 吉吉资源变态 操美女美穴 se情wuyue天 肌肉女做爱英文 色哥哥无码性爱电影 黄色直播网 91gav永久网址 丁香花五月婷婷开之人与兽心 在线大鸡吧干小骚货翻白眼小说 美女做爱亲热图 染岛贡强奸 春色天乃水 樱井莉亚人 求手机黄网啊 色五月开心五月五月天 东京热多少集 东京热0108 不错东京热 俺去啦酒色网 黄色小说酒色网 javhd 长泽あずさ oumeixingai 妈妈与儿子16p 就爱母亲 小骚女影视 家庭乱伦A片 五月天123 哥也撸 婷婷网 乐途旅游网 爱情动作片网站你懂的 哥也要 爱我久久 grch系列在哪有 3344wv亚洲 啪啪啪漫画书网址 又黄又色裸美女影院 能考A片的网站 桃花色热热色综合网 谷露影院日韩 动态图片亚洲在线 色和尚久久爱久久瑟 snis-937在线 伊凡综合成人 gav成人免安装播放 2018秋霞理论电网在线视频 特殊任务 葵 国语爱爱迅雷 magnet 啪啪啪激情黄片视频 情人节快乐视频大奶子女人是谁 秋霞理伦片 下载 人妻熟女婷婷开心影院 羞羞影院每日黄片 群交影院yy834 小学女生三级湿影院 日本情视频高清在线观看讨厌马赛克 日日看超碰在线91 影音先锋乱伦小说 日韩 网红 福利 自拍 另类 又幼穴 樱井莉亚菊门 淫色人妻老司机在线播放 强行占有美女 AV日本电影 湿湿影院网址 在线小萝莉 教师妈妈A片 天昊影院理论片 欧美人兽操逼 巨乳少妇视屏在线 谭干聪 优京香 香澄遥美人女教师 热的 综合 另类 吹潮 抖阴国际版成人电影 久久鸭AV色和尚 涂油av 色噜噜插 云拇指智能视频 A级片i子片 1四虎影剧在线播放 51涩涩 高清国产自拍 在线视频 小清影院AV 999国产厕所偷拍视频 一本道视频穴 国产偷拍主题宾馆在线 被大鸡吧塞满的视频 能看到美女阴唇的视频 淫荡少妇乱伦电影 曽我绫音-人妻調教爆乳I人妻 国内自拍六十七页 久热国内自拍 鲁鲁影院伦理 自拍在线超碰 AVT迅雷 番号大全 mp4 国产自拍 看片 欧州人体配种视频 白嫩小美女汤圆 AV 老外口交视频在线播放 分分日在视频下载 福利国模视频在线 免费 自拍偷拍初中鲍鱼粉 资源站在线视频播放 120发连续中出集锦手机在线 好屌妞精品偷拍视频 97人人操在线视频 赤井美月 大喷水无码种子 亚洲人人色 都市乱伦; 大洋马磁力链接 下载 妻中密影音先锋资 五月天色欲阁 类似莉莉影院 播色屋官网 巴巴鱼秋霞影视 午夜快乐播 阁夜香做爱动态图 黄色网站在线看蕾姆 男女啪啪啪无住碍漫画 西瓜影院福利社 第四色免费电 传奇影院关于宅 97婷婷色秋霞影院 成人午夜福2000级 蝌蚪剧场 5xdd1com 神马 老子久草在线 欧美成人性 天堂岛av大全 亚洲天啪 尘欲香欲缠双 300mium-086 夜剧场 福利视频 西瓜影音 yinsebiship 福利aV 大学女友10p 大学生破处视频 自拍 东方va在线观看青青 免费做爱香蕉视频 男女在床上日逼不穿内衣内裤一级片三级片a片 黄片 罗莉 啊…用力…快点…好深影院 日本免费a片观看网站 美图赚赚视频福利在线 视频直播百度网盘 日空姐免费观看 youjizz动漫视频 伦理福利5400 韶姬胡萝卜在线看 周末情趣影院 精品福利漫画 上原亚衣在线高清 水萝拉家庭教师 mp4 温柔的谎言 磁力 日本动漫 搜一搜 欧美性,交小片 5x社区韩国女主播 大香蕉视频高清无吗 wwwdydognet127001 素人街搭音乐教师在哪里能看 成人 国产 自拍网站 少妇偷拍点播在线 卵蛋网我差点 女孩影院 西瓜影音 大香蕉一到九色 新井佑美 在线播放 天色综合av sao250con 1900 贺立有和刘宝玉操逼出水视频免费体检区 色偷拍自怕亚洲在线97 明星资源视频 56qao免费视频视频 萝莉你懂的2019 射精管理机器人 asmr 久久巨乳在线看 与单位女同事宾馆开房偷情 百度云福利微视频 青欲乐视频 久久影院se 月经期的黄色视频裸体交配 aiss—速度福利网 欧养在线i免费视频 女孩被强暴 手指9191 东京热,一本道免费无码 h里番网站 三级片韩国叫床 大屁股女神叫声可射技术太棒了 在线 秋霞电影伦理伦理片瓜皮 999奇米4色在线观看 和尚精油按摩 精品500av导航 2019最新免费的av网址 快播牛逼叉 水岛津实 高潮 chinese tubeboy free 中国浮力视影院 校友会背叛她的订婚-2午夜影院 小老弟影 下载 爱爱电影90l 国产不卡毛片 2018在线看的视频你懂得 胔她屄流淫水 噜噜网噜噜巴噜噜色午夜影院 一本道久豹子影 超碰任你干免费在线 X网网址 国产手机在线福利小视频在线观看 酒色丁香激情人妻小说 午夜群交视频 暴乳女神 西瓜影院小黄片儿 最新艺术片 高义与孙靖 借种 壮汉 偷拍性爱磁力链接 BAAN-136番号 老师和学生腿上挂了安全套里番 gegekan在线看 甘榴影院 1琪琪网伦理片性之道 青青草原绿色华人免费观看 护士、老师、空姐被强奸视频系列 橘优花迅雷在线播放 998dh com大香蕉 操美女思瑞 韩国学生俊男靓女酒店骑马摇摆抽插 苍井空91链接 爆乳女神私人玩物 波多野结衣 种子 不穿内裤西瓜影音 兵兵淫视 爆乳日韩美女视频 xxxww日本 设为首页加入收藏图片区88 008精品视频在线 狐姆姆导航 欧美高清无码 bt种子 欧美日韩特区 手机在线观看美祢藤 艳色网站 琪琪原色原网站大全琪琪影院 三季第一页天天啪 激情片试看60秒 国产爱清大色网 sex特写系列视频 操逼视频在线观看大鸡巴 操逼2 qibishe saozi8t理论片 SNIS-326 magnet xt urn btih vip主播在线福利视频 福利偷拍老司机老狼 校园伦理在线 超碰视频资源免费高清人妻 成人网在线观看 欧美性爱图区 北非欧美性交视频A片免费看 古堡中的性事视频 艾小青福利视频 性感 强奸母亲磁力链接 师大艺术系校花与男友激情视频 纯洁 亚洲 巨乳外教 色女孩综合影院 kkbokk升级访问升级 欧美熟女内射视频 欧美淫荡人妻丝袜av电影 特黄的免费大片录像(俄罗斯) 强奸乱伦三级中文字小视频 俄罗斯男女性生话视频 2019亚洲国内无码偷拍视频 午夜影院成人一级片肉蒲团 一起去吃拉面吧三国影院 成人动漫淫乱电影网 日本三级床呻吟视频 美国欧美伦理43页视频 成人视频制造商 伦理 大片 波多野吉衣一本道DⅴD 操逼在线视频国语 操逼 视频 舔舔 波波兔 磁力 播播影院 sei 操小比视频 插18岁少女开饱视频 国产手机福利人人干 pao555 偷拍福利秒拍福频 让老公插自己小姊妹 骚女在床上搞那个的事的视频要看到屁股和生植气官 日本伦理片在线观看更多 在线国产自拍小姐草 www曰本黄色片 iesp569磁力 情侣偷拍26uuu 1042成人网 大香蕉av万色屋 2018最新av淘宝在线 亚洲港台操逼视频 影音先锋AVss 亚洲成人手机网站 强暴美女磁力链接 下载 能看印度aⅴ视频 美国萝莉黄片 污污污大香蕉 Xxx经典国语网 明日花做爱视频 神马动漫影视午夜免费观看 社区在线长视频播放 AVwanz00790 主播[萌黛] 粉嫩阴蒂 国产自拍youjizz 狠狠摞网友自拍 金八国 国产自拍-亚洲自拍在线观看 马女人与狗2在线播放 欧洲三级艳情在线观看 鲁鲁鲁日日视频免费 猫米大香蕉伊在线mp4 露胸贱视频软件 色色ojsfoe 洛阳小少妇在线视频 少女自慰视频久久 噜噜吧色在线视频 奇米影视盒三级 视频 激情五月bd韩国电影 混血美女自摸和男友激情啪啪自拍诱人呻吟福利视频 火山性爱在线 极品淫逼97影院 键盘福利导航第一 教室男朋友吃我奶好爽 青娱乐在线秒播 激情小说 轮奸处子 极品亚洲欧美成人影院 激情大尺度迷奸片段片段 一个更新快的色综合 种子猫番号库 福利点云视频 色美女免费的视频 a片黄片免费看 护士午夜福利影视 qiqizhongjiebandibabumifeibofang 做爱 小视频 www 69pao 网爆门广东金马国际旅行社张x茹 九尾狐狸m视频女仆在线 汤姆tom四虎 网红刘婷与快递员发生解压包密码 灰毛衣链接密码最新 后入大奶妹子 黑人来中国跟美妞说鸡巴超级大骚货主动约炮鸡巴大也是很好的一件事啊- 黑暗圣经高清无码 好日日中文字幕 后入式插屁眼儿视频 小姐和顾客链接 magnet 明日花绮罗有码视频 萝莉自慰流水福利 偷拍商场女厕所全景磁力链接 magnet wwwdxjav AEEN资源 偷拍自拍在线精品四虎 韩国xo激情插b视频 人体艺术免费菊花 偷拍明星磁力 magnet juseshiping 噜噜噜抽插射射射sex 秋霞伦理手机在一线看片 韩国偷拍视频免费观看 好吊操清平免费视频 姆啪啪 韩国黄主播免费观看视频 国产主播自拍磁力链接bt种子下载 男女肏屄小视频 色色999日韩偷拍写真 夏芽爱莉百度云 手机福利免费成人视频 火影忍者剧场版色色 动漫XXOO视频在线观看 郭思盈磁力 床戏后入直插 女人B脱毛视频 里番douluo123 日韩学生姝美 女三级伦理福利大香 美女扣b在线视频 黄色小漫 阿福av在线 狠狠色在线 天海翼lpz 862在线播放 www57w 猫咪av短视频怎么没了 欧洲亚洲在线成人 papa678 在线观看黄色电影大全 3pornstarmovies 神马影院骚播网 女同拉拉大合集本田岬 咸人免费免播放器视频 神马午夜初夏 北条麻妃丝袜全集ed2k 高清援交做爱视频 汤芳人艺体照 外国女人的比为什么总是没水 人体艺术摄影欧州版 小姨子的丝情袜意3p 经典三级1页电影 1级图片日韩 第一熟女考妣 女人的逼被前男人艹过我和她生出的宝宝会不会和她前男人长得有点像 欧美美毛穴图 把妹妹尻 诱惑人体艺术一级图片 操b色 性虐第1页小说 人体性交写真 最新美国十次啦 丝袜妈妈被狗 偷拍自拍激情农夫导航 磁力链接东京热 强奸乱片网页影音先锋 爱色电影网图片 WWW_570ZZ_COM 激情男操女过程 肥仔影音黄色网站 人体艺术图片动态 肏老女人电影 草逼集 欧美人像顶级大胆人体艺术